The Study of Religion and the Problem of Institutional Racism
In May 2016, Jay
L. Garfield and Bryan W. Van Norden wrote an opinion piece for the New York
Times which challenged the exclusion of non-western voices in Anglophone
philosophy departments (https://www.nytimes.com/2016/05/11/opinion/if-philosophy-wont-diversify-lets-call-it-what-it-really-is.html).
They suggested that such practices of exclusion rested upon institutional
racism which had its foundation in western colonialism and normativity. The exclusion
of, say, Buddhist philosophical voices from departments of philosophy were/are always
value judgement calls – calls which suggested that Buddhist thinkers were not engaged
in activity that was completely rational and/or that the methods used by
Buddhist thinkers were/are not completely rational (Garfield, 2017, xviii).
I do not wish to
engage in a systematic examination of study of religion departmental biases
here; however, I do believe it is justified to suggest that similar
institutional racism exists within our departments. That is, study of religion departments
suffer from a groupthink which is governed by the historical legacies of
western colonialism and western hegemony, which often means thinkers and schools
of thought who seemingly deviate from paradigmatic norms are either modified to
conform to those norms or are ignored altogether. It could be said that such a characterisation is unfair, as studies of non-western schools of thought are
not excluded in study of religion departments as they are in most philosophy
departments. For example, there are many classes at the undergraduate level
which allow students to study Buddhism, Hinduism and so-called indigenous
traditions. But the question is whether one is studying those traditions –
assuming they can be grouped in such a way – as curiosities to be explained
through the use of predominately western theories, or whether they are studied
as equal dialectic partners, in which the conventional logic of such traditions
influences us in ways which cause us to change our academic practice.
As Garfield
(2015) describes in his book Engaging in Buddhist Philosophy, again
coming at the issue from a philosophical perspective:
By “doing Buddhist
philosophy,” I do not mean developing an account of the history of Buddhist
philosophy – the exegetical project of figuring out what Buddhist philosophers
said. Nor do I mean the mere assessment of the cogency of Buddhist
philosophical arguments. Instead, I mean the attempt to address serious
philosophical problems, of interest in their own right, some arising from the
Buddhist tradition itself, some from the West, in conversation with the
Buddhist tradition, taking it seriously as a source of puzzles and of insights,
and taking its horizon of concerns seriously as a backdrop for philosophical
reflection. (320)
A specific
problem for us is that within the study of religion this way of studying
traditions has been deemed inappropriate by critical religion scholars. The
legitimacy of this sense of inappropriateness is often achieved by critical
religion scholars using multiple, though interdependent, dichotomies which
crave out their identity and position in the academy. For instance, critical
religion scholars might argue that Garfield’s approach uses an insider’s, or
even a theological, point of view which uncritically caretakes the Buddhist
tradition. However, such dichotomies do not provide a justified explanation as
to why such engagement is inappropriate.
For instance, Craig
Martin (2012), in his A Critical Introduction to The Study of Religion,
uses the insider/outsider dichotomy to argue that critical religion scholars,
if they are doing their job right, are ‘outsiders, not insiders’ (18). He
suggests that critical scholars ‘take it for granted that as scholars of
religion our job is to study religions, understand how they work, and so on, not
to advance religious agendas or convert people to a particular religious
tradition’ (18; emphases in original). But Martin’s conceptualisation of
insider/outsider dichotomy is logically problematic.
Martin argues
that the point of his critical scholarship ‘is not to make readers more or less
religious – my goal instead is to help them see how societies are constructed
and maintained, especially when those societies contain oppression or
domination’ (18). What is interesting is that Martin also commits to the
standard critical religion thesis that the category of religion is socially
constructed and does not point to an inherently existing object outside of the
social context of language construction (1-6). The question, then, is how does
Martin maintain this commitment to the constructed character of the category of
religion – whose application Martin describes as ‘arbitrary and unsophisticated’
(6) – while also building his critical academic identity on the
insider/outsider dichotomy?
If there are no religions out in the real world, as they are instead figments of unsophisticated academic and popular imagination (6), how does Martin demarcate the boundaries which separate religious insiders and outsiders? To do so would require that one, to a certain extent, essentialise popular understandings of the category of religion and its others – i.e. the secular. But this flies in the face of Martin’s claim that critical scholarship should help others to realise the socially constructed nature of reality and how it often betrays the power relations and interests of the institutions and people involved in such construction.
If there are no religions out in the real world, as they are instead figments of unsophisticated academic and popular imagination (6), how does Martin demarcate the boundaries which separate religious insiders and outsiders? To do so would require that one, to a certain extent, essentialise popular understandings of the category of religion and its others – i.e. the secular. But this flies in the face of Martin’s claim that critical scholarship should help others to realise the socially constructed nature of reality and how it often betrays the power relations and interests of the institutions and people involved in such construction.
Thus, certain
scholars of religion, and the approaches to religion they champion, can unknowingly support institutional structures which prohibit the possibility of a more
inclusive academic debate – and often for no good reason. Here, it is important
to point out that I am not making a sweeping generalisation that the whole of
the study of religion is characterised by a refusal to engage with non-western
thinkers and theories. However, I am suggesting that certain thinkers and
theories - and I am thinking in particular here of Buddhist thinkers and
theories - are excluded for weak reasons, and this feeds into a wider problem
within academia were non-western voices are either not taken seriously or not
listened to at all.
But if we are to
engage with more voices from outside of the west, we must be sure that such engagement
is grounded in the logic of inclusivity and not just diversity. The latter
has been critiqued as tokenistic, where the mere presence of marginalised
groups or people is seen as an achievement. The problem is dominant frameworks
are not sufficiently challenged by the presence of new, previously
marginalised, groups. Conversely, the former references those efforts made to
modify dominant structures in line with the reasoning, workings and ideas of
newly incorporated groups.
Thus, if the study
of religion is going to move away from the institutional racism that affects it
and other departments, a tightrope is going to have to be walked. Such a task
may be aided by using historical-critical methods, but it is important not to
assume that objective interpretations can be achieved. The core point is one of
reflexivity – to acknowledge our positions of power and work towards
correctives to such imbalances. In this way, we can not only start to readjust the
balance of power within our departments but begin to appreciate the value of theories
that arise from outside of the west and their ability to craft new intellectual horizons; a value which is
ignored if they are only treated as exotic historical curiosities.
Jack Lewis
Graham
Comments
Post a Comment