There and Back Again? Religious Studies and the Shadow of Theology
Abstract
In its
current state, the Study of Religion operates as an unstable and confused field
in which, quite often, no differential is made
between critical and confessional approaches. Drawing on collaborative work
with other doctoral colleagues, we hold
that a new Study of Religion is modelled
from Critical Religion, adopting an anti-realist
ontological framework which does not assume that our object of study exists ‘out-there’. Instead, ‘religion’
should be conceived of as a social
construct, a product of language, particular
histories, and intertwining relations of knowledge and power. Following
this, we hold that discourse analysis is taken
up as the primary methodological framework used by academics of
religion. Doing so, we enter into the debate
regarding the nature and position of the Study of Religion as a separate
academic endeavour from that of other social and human sciences.
Introduction
This paper is the result of inquiries into
the status of Religious Studies within the academy, and its approach to, and
understanding of, method and theory, which have arisen from mine and a doctoral colleague – Liam Metcalf-White’s – PhD
research. From our analysis of the multitude of methods
and theories available for religion
scholars, we came to the shared conclusion that, in its current state, Religious
Studies operates as an unstable and confused field in which, quite often, no
differential is made between critical and
confessional approaches. Thus, in this paper, we analyse the possibility of a
split in the academy – conceptualised
using the categories ‘Religious Studies’ and the ‘Study of Religion’. The
former we understand as a critical realist field and the latter an anti-realist
discipline. This dichotomy is rooted in a
historical division – present since the study’s genesis – which we
examine by looking at the early religionist scholars who were integral to
creating a separate academic space that was committed to studying religion. We
then contrast this to the development of critical approaches in the 1990s
whereby the core assumptions of the previous scholars were challenged. In the latter half of this paper we demonstrate
how, despite arguments to the contrary, this division continues to exist
through an analysis of two introductory textbooks.
Early Study of Religion
While non-theological studies of religion occurred from as early
the 19th century, seen, for instance, in the work of Emile Durkheim,
Max Weber, Karl Marx, and William James, we are more interested in what became
called the History of Religions, a separate and definable area of study within
the academy which focused solely on religion. This independent academic
enterprise, born in the 1950s, argued that religion was a unique aspect of life, requiring its own
study and methods. The History of Religions nevertheless claimed, as did the earlier
19th-century studies, that it was non-theological. Thus, History of Religion
scholars wanted to study religion from an ‘objective’ standpoint which
bracketed out truth claims; however, the academic would be favourably disposed
to their object of study – seeing religion as a ‘good’ thing. The manifestation
of this position was seen most explicitly in the History of Religion’s adoption
of the phenomenological method, which, emerging from the philosophical phenomenology
of Heidegger and Husserl, believed there to be inherent realities that exist substantively
outside of human language – only accessible by performing the epoché – in other words, removing human
bias.
A synopsis of this logic can be found in Jerald Brauer’s forward
to The History of Religions: Essays in Methodology (1959). Here Brauer states that:
[The
perspective of the history of religions] upholds the uniqueness and
givenness of vast expanses of human [religious] experience. Unlike
the approach which seeks to reduce all experience
and reality to a few basic ingredients or
principles, this new perspective strives to grasp a given reality in its own
terms, its own uniqueness, and in its
own contexts (viii; emphasis added).
Brauer
here, then, exemplifies the core ontology and epistemology of the History of
Religions. Hence, he claims, first, that religion ought to be understood as both unique and an inherent
fact of life – a fact that is universal no matter context or history. In other
words, Brauer subscribes to a realist ontology which holds that objects are universal, unchanging, exist independently of
the mind and language, and have an intrinsic
characteristic which gives them
definition. Second, Brauer claims that to understand this realist
reality it must be studied in its own right and therefore engages in
epistemological realism, which holds that there need to be unique methods which
can get at the heart of reality without due influence – this method, as stated
above, was phenomenology.
Thus, History
of Religions was realist attempt to understand religion, which helped facilitate
the development of the first religion departments, as we understand them today,
as separate and legitimate from theology and other social scientific
disciplines. However, this school of thought’s legitimacy began to be critiqued
and undermined, starting in the 1970s but
gaining prominence in the 1990s. The scholars who critiqued the History of Religion
method belong to the critical study of religion.
One of
the first critical religion scholars was Jonathan Z. Smith. In his article Religion,
Religions, Religious (1998), Smith argued that instead of religion existing
in a realist sense, its semantic content was constructed predominantly in sixteenth-century Europe, exported worldwide
through the processes of colonialism – as seen in the World Religions Paradigm –
and now globalisation and capitalism. Thus, Smith states that:
“Religion”
is not a native category. It is not a first-person term of self-characterization. It is a category imposed
from the outside on some aspect of native culture. It is the other, in these
instances, colonialists, who are solely responsible for the content of the
term. (282)
Rather
than peddling a realist view of religion, then, the critical study of religion
argues for an anti-realist perspective. This ontological and epistemological
framework does not assume that our object of study,
religion, exists ‘out-there’. Instead, ‘religion’ should be conceived of as a social construct, a product of language and discourse, particular
histories, and intertwining relations of knowledge, power, and ideology.
In other words, religion is understood
through the prism of social constructivism whereby the relation between the
signified (the object of religion) and the signifier (the term ‘religion’) is seen as co-dependent. The signifier
constructs the signified; the signifier does not point to a signified that
exists ‘out-there’ independent of human discourse and language.
So far,
we have articulated two positions. The first, is the History of Religions
approach, characterised in terms of understanding religion using
phenomenological methods and realist ontologies. An approach mainly sympathetic to the constructed
narratives of those individuals and groups that we study as religious. The
second, is the critical study of religion, which deconstructs the category of
religion – demonstrating it to be socially and
strategically constructed by language alongside other equally
problematic classifications in this semantic web such as ‘secular’, ‘politics’,
‘economics’, ‘science’, etc.
We hold
that this dichotomy should be conceptualised using the categories ‘Religious
Studies’ and the ‘Study of Religion’ – where Religious Studies stands for a field (a culmination of multiple
disciplines and methodologies) in which, quite often, due to realist
commitments, no differential is made between critical and confessional
approaches. On the other hand, the Study of Religion stands for a critical, anti-realist endeavour, focused on
discourse and the strategic formation of identities labelled religious or not.
Contemporary period: A comparison
between two introductory textbooks
Several
scholars have argued that this dichotomy, between Religious Studies and the
Study of Religion, is a false one. The
dichotomy, they argue, is a theoretical one – or debates regarding the lack of
theory. Thus, while in the past Religious Studies, they acknowledge, lacked
theoretical rigour – in the sense that scholars did not theorise the category
of religion as seen for example in the epoché approach which actively
shunned any theoretical engagement – today it is not possible to engage in
Religious Studies without completing courses in method and theory; specifically
at postgraduate level but also trickling down into undergraduate degree courses
(Hughes, 2018).
Despite
this turn toward method and theory in Religious Studies, the dichotomy we have established
is not a false one. Instead, an examination of two introductory textbooks in
the Study of Religion – that both claim to be theoretical – demonstrates how
persistent these problems can be. We will finish this paper, then, by looking
at Bradley Herling’s A Beginner’s Guide to the Study of Religion and
Russell McCutcheon’s Studying Religion: An Introduction – both published
within the last three years – and how they answer two fundamental questions:
‘Why study religion? and ‘How do we study religion?’
The
first question is an ontological one. Herling opens his book by tackling this query
head-on. He muses why, in the 21st
century, Religious Studies is needed. As
he points out, and as you may be aware, there is a common view that religion is
losing its social influence in the contemporary world – a process called
secularisation. The quintessence of this view can be seen in Friedrich Nietzsche’s quote that ‘God is dead’. However,
Herling counters these claims with the following argument:
Despite
those who have predicted and sometimes
hoped for its disappearance, this strange, familiar thing keeps showing
up, calling out for examination, not as something that is dead or dying,
but as a thriving reality – something that, at the very least, we must
live with. (emphasis added)
Thus,
despite the prostrations of some contemporary scholars, Herling’s arguments are
remarkably like those put forward seventy years ago by History of Religion
scholars. Both see religion as universal as demonstrated by Herling’s idea that
although unfamiliar cultures may confront us,
we nevertheless feel instinctively acquainted with something that lies behind
them – which also lies behind our own culture – i.e. religion. He also believes
religion to be a reality which exists outside of language, something which has autonomy.
For instance, he suggests that religion can ‘show up’, can grab our attention by ‘calling
out’, and is something we must live alongside. Thus, we see once again the
logic of realist ontologies which underpins these studies of religion.
Conversely,
Russell McCutcheon suggests that we should study religion, not because of the
above, but rather, as with J.Z. Smith, due to ‘religion’ existing first and
foremost in acts of classification; classification, which he suggests ‘is
hardly an innocent business; [but] instead, […] tied up with issues of power
and identity’ Thus, McCutcheon opens the first chapter of his book with the
following:
Readers
beware: this opening chapter is not about religion. Come to think of it,
despite what many readers might think, neither are all of the other chapters.
Instead, they are about some of the issues involved in defining an object of
study – whatever that object of study may be. Although in our case it happens
to be a collection of claims, behaviours, and institutions that many people
today know by the name ‘religion’...
When
McCutcheon says that this chapter is not about religion, he means religion in a realist sense – as understood by
Herling. Instead, McCutcheon views religion as a name deployed strategically by
human actors – not an aspect of life which interests us because it calls out to
us, but a category useful for maintaining boundaries and assigning semantic
connotations which suit particular interests. Thus, when it comes to the issue
of why we study religion, and the ontological logic behind that, we see that
what Herling and McCutcheon bring to the table are entirely different theories.
The next
question is choosing how to study religion – i.e. an epistemological issue. And again, Herling and McCutcheon have polarising suggestions. For instance, on theory,
Herling states that good scholarship ‘begins as an attempt to look at religion
differently, to see it more clearly, to get at what’s really going on… This process is all about
improving our understanding and discerning the meaning and significance behind the “facts”’. Thus, for Herling,
knowledge of religion is acquired by removing critical judgment and getting to
the “heart” of the object of study by cleaning away the apparent distortions
made by culture and social practices. Religion has, therefore, at its core,
universal and essential meaning, as stable as the object itself. This understanding
of theory and method is practically identical to the History of Religion’s
understanding of phenomenology.
McCutcheon, in contrast, argues that ‘classifications often
tell us far more about the classifier who is naming things in the world than
they do about the item being named’, and, as a consequence, companions ‘discourse
analysis’ – a method which argues, in this context, that because there is no
religion outside of human construction, no study can ‘safely go beyond the
investigation of the uses to which notions of religion are put in social
life’ (Beckford, 2003, 18). Instead, discourse analysis argues that it is
better ‘to map the varieties of meaning attributed to religion in social
settings, to discern the relative frequency of the prevailing meanings and to
monitor changes over time’ (20). Thus, rather than defining religion as a means
by which to point to some essence beneath human culture, a discursive approach
refuses to define the object of study and
instead studies how terms are deployed and for what reasons.
In
summary, then, from an analysis of these two introductory texts and their
approaches to the most fundamental questions, ontological and epistemological,
there is not only a difference of tone but
a significant contrast which makes these two approaches incompatible. Thus, the
dichotomy we established, between Religious Studies and the Study of Religion,
still exists today, and, in our view, cannot be papered over with a ‘big tent’
approach. The so-called ‘big-tent’ in the academy is untenable and is already
starting to fall apart – seen, for example, in the establishment of rival
academic societies, conferences, and journals which actively attack other each for not engaging in ‘proper
scholarship’. Though, this also has
implications for those completing degrees in Religious Studies, as students
move from class to class learning irreconcilable ways to study religion.
Concluding
Remarks
From our perspective as early year researchers, a split
within the academy is preferable to maintaining the present unstable,
status-quo relationship. Thus, to conclude, we argue that current Religious
Studies departments transform into Study of Religion departments, where the
Study of Religion is understood as a discipline – an area of study with an
underlying commitment to social theory, anti-realism, social constructivism and
discourse analysis as its primary method. What counts as Religious Studies now,
however, should not to abandoned as illegitimate. Instead, we hold that this
confused field moves into other, already existing, academic departments, for
instance, sociology, psychology, etc.
Ours may seem like an extreme position to take – an uncompromising
means of using institutional structures to legitimise what we see as ‘good’ scholarship
in religion against scholarship we do not view as such. However, our commitment
to this position is not borne out of a mere desire for intellectual purity. Instead,
we are also concerned with the practical and moral implications of this debate.
For instance, what is an undergraduate or postgraduate student to do when
encouraged to read a book, such as Christopher Deacy’s Christmas as Religion, which asks whether Christmas is a
religion – assuming some prefixed and universal category exists to enable us to
make such normative claims – and then another book, such as James Beckford’s Social
Theory and Religion, which
would instead ask us to critically question the motivations of both scholars
and the public behind such questions as whether Christmas is religion. For
some, this may seem like a pedantic nuance. However, as we have demonstrated in
the previous sections, there are
fundamentally different ontological and epistemological logics that underline
these two books, the questions asked, and the results produced.
There is also, despite the lack of attention paid to this
point, a moral
dilemma to these issues. As Monica Miller states, ‘Reified notions of culture
[religion, gender and race] … are often at the root of systems of violence and
war, […] as well as the icons and indices used to chart violence and the
meanings attached to violence’ (5). Evidence for Miller’s arguments can be seen
in the discourse over the so-called ‘Clash of Civilisations’ which partly
justifies the ‘War on Terror’ and is also part of the logic behind far-right populist
movements in Europe and America. These issues, being of such importance, warrant
not only the establishment of a dichotomy between Religious Studies and the
Study of Religion on a level of theoretical typologies
but also a corresponding split within the
academy.
Jack Lewis Graham and Liam
Metcalf-White
This paper was due to be
delivered at the University of Chester Postgraduate Symposium, 2019;
however, due to illness, this was not possible. The paper has, therefore, been
published here so that the arguments we wished to make on that day are not
lost.
Comments
Post a Comment